OMNIVERSE THEORY WEBPAGES

 

§ TOP OF PAGE [before PART ONE]

§ PART ONE [“Omniverse In The First Person”]

§ PART TWO [“Extraterrestrial Turning Point”] (PART TWO IS ON ITS OWN WEBPAGE)

§ SOME RECENT WORKS BY DR. TANDY [list of works]

§ SOME ADDITIONAL RELATED WORKS [list of works]

 

(PART TWO IS ON ITS OWN WEBPAGE: THE PRESENT PAGE)

------------------------------

 

§ PART TWO

(Tandy, 2011)

 

Tandy, Charles (2011). “Extraterrestrial Turning Point: From Man-unkind to Meridian-kind?” Applied Ethics Review, Volume 50 (April 2011). (ISSN 10282483). (Pages 27-72). [The version below was a pre-publication draft:]

 

 

 

 

ABSTRACT

Extraterrestrial Turning Point: From Man-unkind to Meridian-kind?

Charles Tandy

      It is concluded that the philosophy of Albert Camus provides insight helpful to the ethical-political development and application of (Charles Tandy’s) Omniverse Theory. Such insights help expand Omniverse Theory with respect to pragmatic proposals meant to improve terrestrial society, ban extraterrestrial weapons, and proactively structure an extraterrestrial world at stable peace fit for free persons living in self-sufficient green-habitat intentional communities. Conceptually, it was found that individual rights are ethically required and that these individual rights in turn ethically require mutual obligations. Such a perpetually-evolving peaceful-and-free world society (“Meridiankind”) cuts across generations, generating an ethical imperative to develop anti-death science-technology with the ability to resurrect all of the dead.

      KEYWORDS: Camus (Albert Camus); human nature; obligations; omniverse theory; peace; political philosophy; Rawls (John Rawls); resurrection; rights; Singularity (as in Technological Singularity).

 

Extraterrestrial Turning Point: From Man-unkind to Meridian-kind?

Charles Tandy

§1     Introductory Explanation

      The intent of this article is to add more depth to Omniverse Theory. Omniverse Theory (“Omniverse in the First Person”) was previously presented by me in this publication; therein (Tandy 2009: 21), I suggested that we may “soon achieve a higher personhood and become advanced, extraterrestrial, transmortal beings” – and I attempted to articulate relevant ethical-political implications. Herein below I look at the philosophic works of Albert Camus and conclude that they provide further axiological insight helpful to the ethical-political development and application of Omniverse Theory. With such Camusian insights in mind, I then in effect re-articulate and expand the subsection 8B entitled “From terrestrial beings to extraterrestrial beings” (Tandy 2009: 24-28).

      The 14 sections of the paper are divided into three parts: In PART A, the thought of Albert Camus is explored in prospect of improving Omniverse Theory and of developing feasible approaches to world betterment. The philosophy of Camus, as herein analyzed, is useful to the further development of Omniverse Theory, but lacks refined philosophic details and is very sparse with respect to practical applications. PART B, now engaged in Camusian thoughts, attempts to remedy the lack of philosophic details by focusing on the concepts of individual rights and intentional communities. PART C, informed by PARTS A and B, claims to offer feasible approaches to world betterment. Indeed, PART C argues that humanity is at an unprecedented turning point in history, but whether we will transform ourselves from “Man-unkind” into “Meridian-kind” is a question.

      Specifically, the 14 sections of the present paper are as follows:

§1     Introductory Explanation

PART A: CAMUSIAN THOUGHTS

§2     Albert Camus as Philosopher

§3     Camus and Absurdity: The Myth of Sisyphus

§4     Camus and Anti-Absurdity: The Rebel

§5     Camus as the First Man

PART B: PROJECT-ORIENTATED RE-FORMULATION

§6     Individual Rights and the Right to Intentional Communities

PART C: THE UP-TO PROJECT

§7     From Unintentional Communities to Intentional Communities

§8     The UP-TO Project and Human Nature

§9     Note on Terminology – “Peoples” and “Well-ordered Peoples”

§10   The “UP”: Union of Well-ordered Peoples

§11   The “TO”: Treaty Organization Acting for a Better Cosmos

§12   Extraterrestrial Turning Point

§13   From Man-unkind to Meridian-kind?

§14   Closing Remarks

PART A: CAMUSIAN THOUGHTS

§2     Albert Camus as Philosopher

      In The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy by Douglas Adams, Deep Thought (a supercomputer) spends some time in deep thought about the Ultimate Question of Life, the Universe, and Everything. Indeed, after millions of years, Deep Thought finally provides the answer. The “answer” is 42. (This is reminiscent of Stephen Hawking’s “answer”: M-theory.)

     Albert Camus (1913-1960) claims not to have definitive answers to the ultimate questions of life but instead wants to engage in genuine dialogue with the reader. (I use the present tense because his time, “an age of absurdity”, remains our time.) In his view, one may choose to attempt to learn and advance – instead of dangerously leaping to premature certainty. (In an age of absurdity, leaping to premature certainty or engaging in other irrational behavior is a great temptation.) He says that for him the reasonable approach is to admit uncertainty while simultaneously attempting to live his life with integrity (authenticity). Camus admits uncertainty about ultimate questions – but also notes that at a given point in time some things will seem to him more reasonable or less reasonable than other things. Camus argues for, or (so to speak) paints pictures of, what seems reasonable to him. The reader may (so to speak) look at the pictures and agree or disagree.

      Although Camus saw himself primarily as a creative artist in the form of writer, rather than professional philosopher, I will in this paper focus primarily on what are generally recognized as his two major philosophical works: The Myth of Sisyphus and The Rebel. According to Camus, these two works may be identified with the two stages of his intellectual development. Unfortunately, he died (“absurdly”) at the age of 46 (after only two years as a young Nobel Laureate), so we have no stage three in his development. At the age of 17, however, he had already encountered one of his numerous bouts of tuberculosis; at the time there was little treatment available and he thought he was then going to die.  

§3     Camus and Absurdity: The Myth of Sisyphus

                                                 (“Is my life worth living?”)

      So how do we make the transition from an absurd here and an uncertain now – to a vital world of celebration and multiple flourishing? Perhaps nourishing a certain kind of uncertainty and of celebration may help transform an absurd uncertain universe into a flourishing uncertain multiverse or omniverse. Voltaire wrote to Frederick the Great in 1767: "Doubt is not a pleasant condition, but certainty is an absurd one."

      In our history of learning to advance toward dialogue and friendship, we should know by now that one's fundamental beliefs should be held tentatively rather that absolutely. Socrates is said to have been the world's wisest person because he knew that he did not know with certainty, whereas everyone else was certain. Yet Socrates was committed to dialogue and friendship even at the risk of his very life.

      Let us now proceed to dialogue with our friend Albert Camus. We will begin at the beginning by asking with Camus, in his The Myth of Sisyphus, “Is my life worth living?” (2005: 1-2) If one convincingly feels that neither Reason nor Religion nor Science are  traditions that provide a sure path out of the absurd wilderness, then must one conclude that one’s life has no meaning and is not worth living?  

      In a 1955 Preface to The Myth of Sisyphus, Camus tells us that he wrote it in 1940 (during World War Two) and that he has “progressed beyond several of the positions which are set down here;” [perhaps referring to The Rebel?]. He continues: “but I have remained faithful, it seems to me, to the exigency [absurdity?] which prompted them.”  (Camus 1955: vi)

Part One Of Five Parts Is Entitled: An Absurd Reasoning

      I gather that Camus is suggesting that Reason (as in philosophy), Religion (as in Christianity), and Science (as in physics or psychology) are but games compared to the more serious question: “Judging whether life is or not worth living.” (2005: 1) Accordingly, judging “whether or not the world has three dimensions, whether the mind has nine or twelve categories – comes afterwards.” (2005: 2)

      The man who committed suicide had lost his daughter years earlier and had never gotten over it. Her loss had “‘undermined’ him. A more exact word cannot be imagined. Beginning to think is beginning to be undermined.” (2005: 3) On the other hand, the non-suicides “continue making gestures commanded by existence for many reasons, the first of which is habit.” (2005: 4) (Camus notes that humans learn to breathe before they learn to think.)

      Can one live without the eternal or certain values sponsored by Tradition/Authority (Reason; Religion; Science)? Contrary to what authority/tradition (the philosopher or theologian or scientist) may say, an autonomous Camus is able to begin with absurdity without ending there. Camus says that choosing for or against suicide forgets the third option: One can choose to continue questioning instead of ending it with a premature YES or NO. Instead of taking an “either-or” or “all or nothing” approach, why not choose the middle ground of autonomy? Camus fights passionately against the absurdity of death from the (“Mediterranean”) position of cool moderation instead of extreme certainty. (Camus’s Algeria, as had Golden Greece, bordered on the Mediterranean sea.)

      Thus perpetual questioning leads one [Camus] to say NO to mortality. Many of those who say NO to suicide, however, act as if they said YES. Instead of choosing the anti-death moderation of autonomy, they choose the supposed immortality or certainty of a Tradition/Authority (Reason or Religion or Science as an ideology or way of life). They are the living dead.

      So there are the dead and there are the living dead. Camus takes the third way, that of individual autonomy. One does not have to know that The Ultimate Answer to Life, the Universe, and Everything is “63” or “42” (here the living dead have their lively, sometimes deadly, disagreements) in order to value autonomous living. (As for the literal dead, it seems that those of the dead who took an autonomous or anti-death stance were not entirely successful in that they are dead.[1])   The living dead includes those who have not given much thought to the life-death question, including those who consciously or unconsciously avoid the topic. The living dead also includes those who have made a leap of faith to some eternal or absolutist ideology (religious or secular).

      If I may speak in a technical rather than everyday way, we can say that Camus is a moderate in that he is both anti-death and anti-immortality. Unless one joins the living dead and gives up one’s autonomy, it would seem to take an infinite amount of time to achieve immortality. Instead of fantasizing, one can attempt (in one’s finite presentness in an age of absurdity) to take steps against both literal death and living death. Here is the book’s epigram:

O my soul, do not aspire to immortal life, but exhaust the limits of the possible.

-- PINDAR, Pythian iii

      Anti-death autonomy is the middle way between the extremes of literal suicide and the immortal life supposed by the living dead. Recovering the certainty of knowledge is a fantasy of the living dead. Camus is unwilling to give up his anti-death autonomy in favor of such dangerous nostalgia.     

      I can feel a heart within me and I can touch a world: “There ends all my knowledge, and the rest is construction.” (2005: 17) “In psychology as in logic, there are truths but no truth.” (2005: 18) There are three characters in the mortal drama: the irrationality of the world; the human heart’s desire for meaning; and the encounter between the two (absurdity). First comes the feeling of absurdity or meaninglessness, then comes the notion or concept. The perpetual struggle has meaning (!) “only in so far as it [the absurd] is not agreed to.” (2005: 30)

      So what are the consequences of the absurd? Some pretend to forget or ignore it. Some leap to premature suicide. Others leap to unevidenced certainty in Tradition/Authority (one or another ideology of Reason or Religion or Science). Thus there are many ways to escape from the Sisyphusian struggle. Some, however, freely choose autonomy (integrity; authenticity) and continue to continue to continue the struggle against death.              

      But the Camusian rejection of Tradition or Authority or Ideology is a partial one. Sisyphus finds it natural to use experience or tools associated with reason or religion or science to the extent they are helpful in his unending battle against literal death and living death. For example, one can use reason in a piecemeal way to counter both Ideology and Mortality. Camusian moderation maneuvers between the extreme paths of triumphal reason and humiliated reason.

     “The laws of nature may be operative up to a certain limit [prior to individual autonomy], beyond which they turn against themselves to give birth to the absurd [individual autonomy]. Or else, they may justify themselves on the level of description without for that reason being true on the level of explanation.” (2005: 35) But whatever the case may be, Sisyphus will not give up his autonomous anti-death struggle against the universe.

      Sisyphus chooses integrity rather subterfuge. Without appealing to eternal or absolute values, he removes Reason and Religion and Science from their pedestals but does not commit them to annihilation. This is the middle way between the extremes of hubris and humiliation. Autonomous rebellion against death and absurdity is a meaningful and moderate way to perpetually search for meaning.  

      “By the mere activity of consciousness I transform into a rule of life what was an invitation to death.” (2005: 62) Reasoning about the absurd leads Camus to infer three natural consequences for Sisyphus:

1. My Life (my rebellion): “It is essential to die unreconciled and not of one’s own free will.” (2005: 53)

2. My Liberty (my autonomy): inner authenticity (free self-legislation with integrity) instead of external rules (eternal or absolute values) with respect to thought and action.

3. My Pursuit of Happiness (my passion): diversity of experience, “But the point is to live.” (2005: 63)

Part Two Of Five Parts Is Entitled: The Absurd Man

      Camus then attempts to present a few cameos of persons (the seducer-lover; the actor; the adventurer-conqueror) as each might live their very own individual lives of my-rebellion, my-freedom, and my-passion. The Absurd Man does not claim to know about eternal or absolute values; indeed, he has no need of rules to justify his behavior. The Absurd Man finds it difficult to believe that anyone deserves a death sentence, whether from the universe or from other men. Such Absurd Persons live their lives rather than obey someone else’s rules.  

Part Three Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Absurd Creation

      According to Camus, the creator-artist is “the most absurd character.” (2005: 89) Camus may be referring to an artist-writer such as himself. If the world is clear and certain, we get description rather than (absurd) art. Artists prefer images over arguments. Camus wants to create without appeal to eternal or absolute values and thus “liberate my [literary] universe of its phantoms and to people it solely with flesh and blood truths whose presence I cannot deny.” (2005: 99) Even the great writers such as Dostoievsky and Kafka do not altogether succeed in this respect. One of the truly absurd works, Camus says, is Melville’s Moby Dick.

Part Four Of Five Parts Is Entitled: The Myth Of Sisyphus

      Sisyphus was a wise and clever mortal accused of lacking proper respect for the gods. Indeed, he succeeded in putting Death in chains. However the gods then unchained Death and condemned Sisyphus. His punishment was severe: Forever rolling a stone up a mountain only to have the boulder fall back again and again and again. His situation is tragic because he is without hope, forever doomed to failure. YET: “If the descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can also take place in joy. The word is not too much.” (2005: 117) “The struggle itself towards the heights is enough to fill a man’s heart. One must imagine Sisyphus happy.” (2005: 119)

Part Five Of Five Parts Is An Appendix Entitled:

Hope And The Absurd In The Work Of Franz Kafka

      Kafka writes in such a way that it forces the reader to re-read and re-interpret. We find that Samsa has “a ‘slight annoyance’” – “his boss will be angry at his absence.” (2005: 125) Samsa otherwise seems unconcerned – that his body has metamorphosed into that of a huge insect!  

   Camus opines that truth is contrary to conventional morality. Sometimes Kafka seems to almost realize that it is fatal to give God what does not belong to him. But then Kafka will sneak in hope, unaware that hope “is not his business. His business is to turn away from subterfuge.” (2005: 134) 

§4     Camus and Anti-Absurdity: The Rebel

 (“How do I live a meaningful life?”)

      Camus, in his The Myth of Sisyphus, had asked “Is my life worth living?” We have seen that his conclusion was affirmative (or at least it was a passionate NO to NO). Now we will ask with Camus, in his The Rebel, “How do I live a meaningful life?” Here we will find some evolution in his thought.

      Indeed, if you have read only The Myth of Sisyphus, and no other work by Camus, you may declare my interpretation above severely distorted. You may be correct, for I read The Rebel before reading The Myth of Sisyphus. I have read the two volumes as if they were one. Moreover, in my anachronistic fusion of the two, I am not attempting to articulate a definitive Camus interpretation of Camus. That is why PART A’s title says (not “The Thoughts Of Camus”, but) “Camusian Thoughts” – thoughts inspired “about the Ultimate Question of Life, the Universe, and Everything” upon reading these two works by Camus. With this caveat in mind, I now present to you my Camusian Thoughts about The Rebel.

      In the introduction, Camus says that in our peculiar time, good-will (“innocence”) is suspect. It seems these days we have to explain why we want to do good. Camus wants to do good simply because it is the good thing to do. Yet in our complex world, is it even possible to do good without directly or indirectly killing or harming someone? In the face of the absurd, Camus chose to live. But given this, and given our age of ideologies (Reason; Religion; Science), is it possible to live without killing others? Simply by living in an age of ideologies, do we not participate in the literal death or living death of others?

      Yet is it not the case that: “From the moment that life is recognized as good, it becomes good for all men”? (1991: 6)  Not only should one not kill oneself, but likewise one should not kill others. My autonomous or natural rights imply your rights too. My rights and your rights “must be accepted or rejected together.” (1991: 6)

          Choosing to live is a value judgment, a standard or limit with implications for one’s relation to others. When I rebel against absurdity, my action is on behalf of all. My individualistic act is an act of solidarity or unity.  

Part One Of Five Parts Is Entitled: The Rebel

      A rebel is one “who says no, but … who [also] says yes. … there are limits.” (1991: 13) By rebelling, we are saying that there are limits or standards or values or rights which we all should respect. Thus there is a sense in which we are all naturally equal and “a human nature does exist.” (1991: 16)  Humans have metaphysical solidarity – they are a natural community: My rebellion “is for the sake of everyone in the world.” (1991: 16)

      The spirit of rebellion tends not to be expressed in societies of either extreme inequality or extreme equality. But over time we humans experience absurdity, and humanity’s self-awareness grows. Yet we are tempted to forget either the basis of rebellion or that there are limits. We tend to ideologically leap into a living death – either groveling before God or intoxicating on power.     

      I, Camus, rebel against both servitude and tyranny. I, Camus, refuse to give in to either metaphysical other-worldliness or to Caesaristic historicism. In order to exist, we humans must rebel: “Man’s solidarity is founded upon rebellion, and rebellion, in its turn, can only find its justification in this solidarity.” (1991: 22)

      Thus we have gone beyond individualistic absurdity. Descartes had said: “I think – therefore I am.” But in rebellious solidarity, “suffering is [now] seen as a collective experience. … I rebel – therefore we exist.(1991: 22)

Part Two Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Metaphysical Rebellion

      The Man refuses to give in to metaphysical other-worldliness. The Man refuses to ideologically leap into a living death, groveling before God. To the “I rebel, therefore we exist,” the Man adds: “And we are alone.(1991: 104)

Part Three Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Historical Rebellion

      The Man refuses to give in to Caesaristic historicism. The Man refuses to ideologically leap into a living death, intoxicating on tyrannical power. To the “I rebel, therefore we exist,” and the “We are alone,” the Man adds: “Live and let live.” “Instead of killing and dying in order to produce the being that we are not, we have to live and let live in order to create what we are.” (1991: 252) Thus the key importance of creativity or art:

Part Four Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Rebellion And Art

      Creation or art is pure rebellion – it demands unity while partially rejecting the world. The world is used by the artist in order to attempt to create a better world that meaningfully unites everyone and everything. The Protestant Reformation, the French Revolution, Russian nihilism, and German ideology are all examples of artistic banishment. Should we not choose morality or usefulness or progress (take your pick) over beauty?

      The artist rebels against these stark, narrow worlds – by constructing alternatives to such prisons. The artist believes in life and living, not death and dying. “Rebellion … is a fabricator of universes.” (1991: 255) The artist finds both absurdity and beauty in the world. This suggests construction of a less absurd, more beautiful universe. Thus the artist becomes part of the process of evolution.

      The modern novel “competes with creation and, provisionally, conquers death.” (1991: 264)  Proust’s Time Regained “appears to be one of the most ambitious and most significant of man’s enterprises against his mortal condition. … this art consists in choosing the creature in preference to his creator.” (1991: 267) But even more, it supports “the beauty of the world and its inhabitants against the powers of death and oblivion. It is in this way that his rebellion is creative.” (1991: 268)

      Real creation attempts neither to escape from reality nor to accept it as it is. The moderation and passion of the Meridian Rebel or true artist “simply adds something that transfigures reality.” (1991: 269) Thus both “formal’ art and “realist” art must be seen as extremes. Much “modern” art unwisely attempts to replace one totalitarian “unity” with another. The Meridian artist intervenes to make the world more beautiful, between the extremes of leaving the world as it is either by pure description or by pure escapism.

      Real literary creation is not to be identified with commentary or criticism. Terror and tyranny contradict creativity and art. Perhaps a renaissance of creativity and civilization is possible. Often movements proclaiming a new world are actually the extreme opposite or climaxing contradiction of the old one. Today this extreme, in one form or another, is bent on industrial production. But: “The society based on production is only productive, not creative.” (1991: 273)

      Every creative act of love denies the world of master-slave. Yet today it seems our leaders have no time for love. “But the fact that creation is necessary does not perforce imply that it is possible.” (1991: 274)  Of every ten potential artists, maybe one or none will become artists if all that counts is industrial competition in a hellish world.   

      Even if history has an end, it is not our task to end it. Those who choose to ignore nature or the sea or the stars or beauty are constructing a world devoid of freedom and dignity. We, the Meridian rebels, must uphold beauty and creativity if we are to live in a beautiful and creative world with freedom and dignity.

 Part Five Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Thought At The Meridian

      Forgetting its Meridian roots (I rebel – therefore, we are), rebellion too easily oscillates between murder and sacrifice. If a “single human being is missing in the irreplaceable world of fraternity, then this world is immediately depopulated. … On the level of history, as in individual life, murder is thus a desperate exception or it is nothing.” (1991: 282) Killing and rebellion are contradictions; death and life are contradictions.

      “Rebellion is in no way the demand for total freedom. On the contrary, … the rebel wants it to be recognized that freedom has its limits everywhere that a human being is to be found … The more aware rebellion is of demanding a just limit, the more inflexible it becomes. … The freedom he claims, he claims for all; the freedom he refuses, he forbids everyone to enjoy. He is not only the slave against the master, but also man against the world of master and slave.” (1991: 284)  Indeed, “rebellion, in principle, is a protest against death.” (1991: 285)

      But in the real, absurd world in which we live, the rebel is confronted with hard choices. Violence versus non-violence. Justice versus freedom. And: Not to choose is itself a choice or risk. “In so far as it is a risk it cannot be used to justify any excess or any ruthless and absolutist position.” (1991: 289)

       Rebellion with limits changes everything: We all have a common nature and individual rights. But technology, without proper guidance from the rebel, does not know this. Science has forgotten that it originated in rebellion with limits. Science and technology may yet return from deadly extremes to their origins and serve “individual rebellion. This terrible necessity [against terrorism, destruction, and enslavement] will mark the decisive turning-point” in history. (1991: 295)

      The value that gives historical development meaning is not unknown: I rebel – therefore, we are. Thus: “Virtue cannot separate itself from reality without becoming a principle of evil. Nor can it identify itself completely with reality without denying itself.” (1991: 296) We have here a new form of virtue and a new kind of individualism. “I have need of others who have need of me and of each other. … the individual, without this discipline, is only a stranger … I alone, in one sense, support the common dignity that I cannot allow either myself or others to debase. This individualism is in no sense pleasure; it is perpetual struggle, and, sometimes, unparalleled joy when it reaches the heights of proud compassion.” (1991: 297)

      The moderation of the rebel, Meridian Man, is a perpetual tension and never-ending task. Contradictions ensue if we try to exist either above or below the meridian. History and the future must be viewed as opportunities, not as objects of worship. Passionate rebellion with limits is Meridian Man’s approach to such opportunities. “Even by his greatest effort man can only propose to diminish arithmetically the sufferings of the world. But … no matter how limited they are, they will not cease to be an outrage. … confronted with death, man from the very depths of his soul cries out for justice.” (1991: 303) This applies not only to literal death, but also to living death: “Thus Catholic prisoners, in the prison cells of Spain, refuse communion today because the priests of the regime have made it obligatory in certain prisons.” (1991: 304) Thus moderation and life perpetually struggle against extremity and death.     

      Now to the final paragraph of The Rebel (1991: 306): Meridian Man refuses the temptation of Caesaristic intoxication “in order to share in the struggles and destiny of all men,” birthing a strange joy; happily “we shall remake the soul of our time … which will exclude nothing.” Following the intoxicating “pride of a contemptible period”: “All may indeed live again, … but on condition that it is understood that they correct one another, and that a limit, under the sun, shall curb them all. … it is time to forsake our age and its adolescent furies.” At “this moment … at last … [the first] man is born.”

§5     Camus as the First Man

      Camus, age 46, died absurdly as a passenger in an automobile accident in 1960. With him was his uncompleted manuscript, The First Man. I suggest that it is only by each one of us learning to become the first man that each one of us can become the first man – neither slave nor tyrant. With Camus, we may yet learn to become Meridians – passionate, moderate rebels. If Camus is right, our common task – the struggle against death and the birthing of Mankind or Meridiankind – is an occasion of strange joy.

PART B: PROJECT-ORIENTATED RE-FORMULATION

§6     Individual Rights and the Right to Intentional Communities

      When Camus rebels against absurdity, his action is on behalf of all. His individualistic act is an act of solidarity or unity. His autonomous rights imply your individual rights too. (Otherwise, an assertion of rights is an assertion about power, not about rights.)

      Buford (1984: 187) points out that: “For Lou to have a moral right to do x, someone else is morally obligated to act or refrain from acting regarding x if Lou wants that person to do so.” On the one hand, “where there is an obligation there is not necessarily a right.” On the other hand: “Wherever there is a right to something there is a corresponding duty or obligation to [attempt to] honor that right.” 

      Thus the interactive perspective of individual moral rights, properly understood, views persons as social beings instead of as egoistical atoms. Buford (1984: 189-190) elaborates:

·       “First, the practice of rights presupposes that all participants accept and follow rules that are social in character.”

·       “Second, the practice of rights enmeshes one in a social structure. ... Such autonomy, when it is present, always exists within some social structure.”

·       “Third, the practice of rights necessarily involves acceptance of authority and subordination to that authority. ... [We are] obligated to do the best that we know [as in the rule: “one should not kill other people”] and submit to its authority.”

·       The “practice of rights occurs only within a society [of mutual obligations].”

·       “If I have the right to speak freely in a town meeting, you are obligated to allow me that freedom. But you would not want to congratulate yourself on your generosity in allowing me to speak. ... [Rights] are accorded you by right, not by my generosity.”

·       Accordingly: “Respect for the rights of others does not involve loyalty or friendship.” Yet: “In love and friendship we often [so to speak] give up rights and subordinate and sacrifice ourselves. We do such things willingly.”

      Based on Camus and on Buford, we may now articulate some of our findings with respect to individual (moral) rights and intentional (voluntary) communities: Authentically choosing one’s individual rights to life and liberty carries analogous implications for one’s relation to others. The individual rights we identify with life and living mean we have mutual-obligations not to kill each other – our societal environment ought to be one of stable peace devoid of violence, killing, and war. The individual rights we identify with living and liberty mean we have mutual-obligations to insure freedom of thought, of expression, of association, and to pursue happiness. Thus, our mutual-obligation society of individual rights includes the right to live in peaceful and free communities.

PART C: THE UP-TO PROJECT

§7     From Unintentional Communities to Intentional Communities

      It seems that there are two ways which one may (so to speak) give up one’s individual rights and do so reasonably: (1) One way may be seen as related to the concept of “Intentional Communities” (in section 11 below we will talk of a “Society of Intentional Communities”). That is to say, with respect to certain group relationships, one may freely choose to give up rights and subordinate and sacrifice oneself; in this case one may later choose to (so to speak) take back or restore one’s rights again. (2) A second way may be seen as related to the concept of “Society” (in section 11 below we will talk of a “Society of Intentional Communities”). That is to say, a second way to reasonably (so to speak) give up an individual right is by seeing that one was mistaken in viewing it as a right; at first one may think that one has the right to egotistically steal and kill as one chooses, only to later apprehend (say, per Camus) that the “might makes right” view is mistaken. (Rather, a Camusian or a Meridian feels “I rebel, therefore we are.”)    

      Thus it seems that individual (moral) rights and intentional (voluntary) communities are mutually implicated and supportive in our quest for a good society (Buford 1984: 191). By forming intentional communities, “we distinguish ourselves from the rest of society in order to achieve those objectives we personally believe best. We set about to realize our dreams. Within the groups we form by right we can experience the love, warmth, sympathy, and fellow feeling we want.” “What kind of social relations best support the living of the good life? They are those in which the rights of individuals are protected. Since rights can exist only in the context of a society, that society must allow for the formation of families and groups [intentional communities] to promote the realization of objectives the individuals believe best.”

      If we have individual rights to a peaceful and free society of intentional communities, then we have a mutual-obligation to create and sustain such a world society. Heretofore our history has not given us a peaceful and free world of intentional communities. As Camus and history have shown, attempting to produce desirable ends by undesirable means is not the way to learn about rights and obligations or to create and sustain a world peaceful and free. Below I claim that we can use desirable means to achieve desirable ends. As I will demonstrate, the means are dependent on context. We will want, while staying afloat, to devolve our dangerous dinghies and build better boats, sound ships that sail peaceful and free.

§8     The UP-TO Project and Human Nature

      For many centuries it was often said that due to nature or human nature, stable world peace was not possible and perhaps not desirable. For many centuries it was often said that due to nature or human nature, human heavier-than-air flight was not possible and perhaps not desirable. For many centuries it was often said that due to nature or human nature, the banning of human slavery was not possible and perhaps not desirable.

      According to the third-century-BCE Chinese prince and scholar, Han Fei Tzu: “King Yen practiced benevolence and righteousness and the state of Hsü was wiped out; Tsu-kung employed eloquence and wisdom and Lu lost territory. So it is obvious that benevolence and righteousness, eloquence and wisdom, are not the means by which to maintain the state.” (Watson 1964: 100). 

      The so-called “Parable of the Tribes” or “Prisoner’s Dilemma” helps explain why things sometimes go from bad to worse.  Understanding the Parable or Dilemma may help us, individually and collectively, engender a future that goes from good to better instead of from bad to worse. Our apparent inability – in many past centuries – to ban human slavery, to engage in heavier-than-air flight, or to achieve stable world peace cannot be reduced to nature or human nature.

      Schmookler (1984: 21) explains the error of reducing all human problems to nature or human nature; Schmookler explains the Parable of the Tribes this way: “In an anarchic situation … no one can choose that the struggle for power shall cease. … no one is free to choose peace, but anyone can impose upon all the necessity for power. [And humans, unlike nonhuman animals, have the ability to modify their anarchic situation.]”        

      Evans (1995: 719) also explains the error of reducing all human problems to nature or human nature; Evans explains the Prisoner’s Dilemma this way: “The prisoner’s dilemma describes a possible situation in which prisoners are offered various deals and prospects of punishment. The options and outcomes are so constructed that it is rational for each person, when deciding in isolation, to pursue a course which each finds [in terms of actual results] to be against his interest and therefore [in terms of actual results] irrational. … Such a scenario postulates a lack of enforced cooperation; and to avoid the undesirable outcome, the actors in the drama need to be forced into cooperation by a system of [enforced] rules.”

§9     Note on Terminology – “Peoples” and “Well-ordered Peoples

       My “UP-TO” proposal is meant to be a general outline or approach to achieve world peace, freedom, and prosperity. If “the devil is in the details,” I leave such details to those more qualified than I. Nevertheless I have to use words even to suggest the general proposal such as it is. These words may be easily misunderstood. Thus herewith below a preliminary note on terminology. (I suggest consulting The Law of Peoples by John Rawls if one wishes to attempt to improve on the terminology – i.e., the meaning of “peoples” and “well-ordered peoples”.)

       I have chosen to use the word “peoples.” As a first approximation: By “peoples” I mean to include so-called “states” (e.g., members of the United Nations) and so-called “quasi-states” (e.g., Taiwan/ ROC/ Chinese Taipei). Strategic ambiguity and strategic clarity each have their proper roles to play in human life and world betterment. Such decisions of ambiguity or clarity I leave to those actually involved in negotiating to achieve a better world. Given such a concrete context, they (not I) may decide, for example, whether so-called “quasi-states” should be included or whether only so-called “states” should be counted as “peoples.”

    I have chosen to use the term “well-ordered peoples.” As a first approximation: By “well-ordered peoples” I mean to include “democratic peoples” and “decent peoples” (somewhat along the lines suggested by John Rawls in his The Law of Peoples, but so as to be consistent with the previous paragraph). Here again I leave it to those actually negotiating the agreement or treaty to decide, for example, whether “decent peoples” should be included or whether only “democratic peoples” should be counted as “well-ordered.” The UP part of the UP-TO proposal will be identified primarily with the term “well-ordered peoples” (as distinguished from the broader term “peoples”).  The TO part of the UP-TO proposal will be identified primarily with the term “peoples” (as distinguished from the narrower term “well-ordered peoples”).

       Below, I do NOT say that the European Union MUST take the lead to achieve world peace, freedom, and prosperity. Again, I am not the most qualified person to decide this pragmatic question (of leadership in the present context). Nevertheless on this issue I wish now to express my opinion. My opinion is that the European Union should take the lead in achieving world peace, freedom, and prosperity. A detailed defense of this tentative opinion (“that the European Union should take the lead”) is beyond the purview of the present paper. However below I outline an “UP-TO” approach which I believe is doable at the level of international politics. For it to prove successful, it will require assistance from the United States. But I see the project as having a better chance of success if the EU (European Union) takes the leadership role. My belief or opinion is that it is in the interest of the United States and of the world for the United States to encourage the EU to take the leadership role in this unprecedented endeavor. So what exactly is the UP-TO proposal I am so excited about and want the EU and others to implement? First I will describe UP, then I will describe TO.[2]

§10   The “UP”: Union of Well-ordered Peoples

      Immanuel Kant’s Perpetual Peace, published in 1795, is a remarkable piece of social science foresight.[3]  In 1795, very few republics existed and no liberal democracies existed (e.g. consider civil rights issues related to slavery and women). Kant argued for republicanism and for an expanding concert of peaceful republics. He believed this approach (as distinguished from the universal membership approach) would eventually lead (in the 21st century?) to a global stable peace.

      The UP proposal is a proposal for a terrestrial Union of Peoples Well-ordered. On today’s Earth, the People of China and the People of Russia are NOT well-ordered – but the EU Peoples and the North America Peoples, among many others, do have the actual substance of cultural norms and working mechanisms (rather than the mere form of words or documents or elections) that considerably support the rights of persons and that considerably tend to prevent war among such like-minded well-ordered peoples. Reminiscent of Kant, this is sometimes referred to by today’s political scientists as the world’s “zone of peace.”       

      Let me point out that although the UP and the TO are separate entities with separate terrestrial-extraterrestrial functions, they are nevertheless expected, with help from the EU and others, to be birthed on the same date and to be perpetually on speaking terms with each other. Signatories of peoples to the (terrestrial) UP are members of the UP Voting Council; signatories of peoples to the (extraterrestrial) TO are members of the UP Advisory Council. Likewise, signatories of peoples to the (extraterrestrial) TO are members of the TO Voting Council; signatories of peoples to the (terrestrial) UP are members of the TO Advisory Council.       

        The UP (Union of Well-ordered Peoples) idea is inspired in part by the Daalder and Lindsay proposal for a CD (Concert of Democracies). (The article by Ivo Daalder and James Lindsay is entitled “Democracies of the World, Unite”.)[4]    While the UP and the CD concepts are not altogether identical, either realization may be expected to provide a number of benefits to world betterment, including: (1) Strengthening and expanding the positive relationship zone of peace and peaceful activities among UP or CD societies; and, (2) Weakening the negative temptations of UP or CD societies, such as (A) crusading imperialism; (B) imprudent appeasement; and, (C) moralistic isolationism.         

§11   The “TO”: Treaty Organization Acting for a Better Cosmos

      The TO proposal is a proposal for an extraterrestrial Treaty Organization Acting for a Better Cosmos. Before I explain the TO proposal in more detail, let me again point out that although the UP and the TO are separate entities with separate terrestrial-extraterrestrial functions, they are nevertheless expected, with help from the EU and others, to be birthed on the same date and to be perpetually on speaking terms with each other. Signatories of peoples to the (terrestrial) UP are members of the UP Voting Council; signatories of peoples to the (extraterrestrial) TO are members of the UP Advisory Council. Likewise, signatories of peoples to the (extraterrestrial) TO are members of the TO Voting Council; signatories of peoples to the (terrestrial) UP are members of the TO Advisory Council. Note that the People of China and the People of Russia may indeed be founding (voting) members of TO but not of UP; on the one hand, they are peoples – on the other hand, they are not yet well-ordered. (At some point in time in the 21st century, perhaps China and Russia will become well-ordered.)          

      Previously above I have explained the “Union of Peoples Well-ordered” (UP) idea. Now I present the TO (“Treaty Organization Acting for a Better Cosmos”) part of the UP-TO proposal.[5]   I believe that both the UP and TO ideas are desirable and feasible for today’s world, even more so if implemented together (UP-TO). These two Concerts, acting more or less in concert, may have historically unusual (“doubly-synergistic”) abilities to transmute our outmoded world into a “transcivilization” of peaceful prosperous societies. 

        We may not know the actual or secret (classified) policies of the United States and others with respect to extraterrestrial space. It is nevertheless true that over 100 nations (including all of the “major” ones) publicly claim to support the 1967 Outer Space Treaty (or have at least signed it). The purpose of the 1967 Outer Space Treaty is to promote the peaceful uses of outer space. But today, as we approach its half-century mark, the 1967 peace treaty continues to have no enforcement mechanism.  

       The TO would serve two functions: (1) as gateway between planet earth and peaceful space – this includes enforceably banning weapons and weapons-making from extraterrestrial space; and, (2) as midwife to an evolving Extraterrestrial Society

      As I proceed to discuss these two functions, I want to attempt to offer a realistic vision of future extraterrestrial technology. This should help us better understand how to think about TO (and UP-TO). But realistic visions sometimes change. Accordingly, we will want TO to be flexible enough to change in case our “realistic vision” changes!   

      It has been said that if your prediction of far-future technological capacities does not sound like science fiction, then your prediction is wrong. Accordingly, please momentarily assume that the following vision (which may sound like science fiction) is indeed realistic. You can then later critically examine the notes and bibliography to independently decide for yourself. 

      The astounding capacity of future technology can be glimpsed at by taking a non-controversial look at the future of extraterrestrial O’Neill Habitats and of molecular Drexler Technology (and their eventual melding together).[6], [7]    I say non-controversial because the controversy in each case is over when, not if. Thus for present purposes we can overcome this dispute by simply talking non-controversially about these kinds of capacities in the far future (bypassing timeline predictions of near or far). Abundant extraterrestrial resources will be used to construct greener-than-earth, self-sufficient, self-replicating O’Neill Habitats in orbit around planets and suns. Accordingly, barring catastrophe, it seems highly likely that in the long run almost all of our multitudinous offspring will be permanently living and working somewhere in the universe other than on planet Earth. Indeed, molecular Drexler Technology is not required for construction and development of extraterrestrial O’Neill Habitats (“SEG communities”) – it just makes the task easier.     

        Historically one of the reasons that Terrestrial civilizations of old engaged in wars against each other was to gain more territory, and the power and glory that came with empire. (Human-caused global warming, human-made weapons of mass death and destruction, and a human-crowded global village did not yet exist.) As life grew denser on planet earth, the environment on which each organism depended increasingly consisted of other living things. But the development of advanced O’Neill Habitats (Sustainable Extraterrestrial Greener-than-earth communities, or SEGs) in orbit around a planet or a sun will mean multiple, self-reproducing biospheres; "unlimited free land” (freely available territory); and the realistic possibility of intentional (i.e., voluntary) communities for all persons. Instead of remaining in the community or culture of one's birth, one will be realistically free to experiment living in one kind of community or another. New kinds of cultures and communities will be enabled by the new extraterrestrial technology.

      According to Carter and Dale (1974: 12): “Most of the progressive and dynamic civilizations of mankind started on new land – on land that had not been the center of a former civilization.” The following metaphorical insights have been widely quoted by SEG experts: "The Earth was our cradle, but we will not live in the cradle forever." "Space habitats [SEGs] are the children of Mother Earth." According to Carl Sagan, our long-term survival is a matter of “spaceflight or extinction”; all civilizations become either space-faring or extinct. According to the “mass extinction” article in The Columbia Encyclopedia (6th ed.): “The extinctions, however,  did  not  conform  to  the  usual  evolutionary rules  regarding who  survives;  the  only  factor  that  appears  to  have  improved  a family  of  organisms’  chance  of  survival  was  widespread  geographic colonization.”[8]

Gateway Between Planet Earth And Peaceful Space

      The TO would serve as gateway between planet earth and peaceful space – this includes enforceably banning weapons and weapons-making from extraterrestrial space. 

        As explained above, eventually there will be many Extraterrestrials, few Terrestrials. We can understand the practical or special interests that might prevent us from banning weapons and their manufacture from today's Earth. Indeed, someday there might be analogous practical or special interests in extraterrestrial space unless we engage in foresight today to proactively and enforceably ban weapons and their manufacture from extraterrestrial space.

          On the one hand, our political interests today may constrain us in our present time and place. But, on the other hand, our political interests today may free us with respect to future times and places (e.g. our extraterrestrial future). What this means is that today we have a realistic prospect of proactively establishing the legal structure and enforcement powers needed for a world at stable peace in extraterrestrial space.

        If we wait until later, we may not be so free to "do the right thing" and establish stable peace in extraterrestrial space. Extraterrestrial space is immense; it is all of the universe except for a single small planet. Eventually it might even become feasible to extend stable peace to planet Earth and thus the entire universe.

        It is my belief that the suggested Extraterrestrial Space Treaty Organization (TO) will make a fine gift to our offspring and, by the way, help present Earthlings as well. But if we want a good world at stable peace (whether that world be Terrestrial Civilization or Extraterrestrial Transcivilization), it would seem we must be willing to unblinkingly face up to the following questions: Is stable peace possible if each person or each people is passionately convinced that their worldview is basically good and correct – and that other worldviews are evil or bad or incorrect? If we could enforceably prevent each and every person from killing any person over a conflict (say, a conflict of worldviews), would we do so? If so, how would we resolve our conflicts fairly or justly?

      One advantage we have in facing up to these difficult questions is that we can use our imaginations to futuristically view ourselves as Extraterrestrials living in intentional communities (SEGs or O’Neill Habitats). We can further assume that a political structure there and then exists that we describe as a good world at stable peace. These Extraterrestrials of the future have liberties and technologies that Terrestrials do not have today. Yet humans today have the ability and perhaps the practical political will – via the TO proposal – to help insure humanity’s non-extinction and promote human flourishing in a free and prosperous world at stable peace in extraterrestrial space (almost all of the universe).

        I will assume that it is a fact that if today's Terrestrials are to produce such an extraterrestrial Treaty Organization (including effective enforcement provisions), it will require agreement from a number of Peoples. How many persons or peoples would accept or endorse a Space Treaty that effectively and enforceably bans weapons and their manufacture from extraterrestrial space? In this context (a good and practical legacy to our offspring), I should think we should be diligent enough to rally enough supporters. For example, TO might be signed originally by, say, twenty Peoples (including most of the "major" ones). But the Treaty would be strongly effectively enforced by TO’s Agency for a Better Cosmos (ABC) – NOT by Peoples/States – against ALL and EVERYONE, whether or not they sign the Treaty. Once in force, I would expect many others to sign on – since the Treaty applies to them even if they do not sign it. Sooner or later the Treaty really would have to be strongly effectively enforced by the ABC against all and everyone, because eventually persons and communities will permanently settle in extraterrestrial space. (Such a Treaty also offers hope and inspiration to those of us of the present.)

        Okay, you may say, this is a reasonable enough start, but what other liberties, responsibilities, and political structures would be appropriate for the Extraterrestrial World? So far, what we presumably have is a partial prototype for an Extraterrestrial World at stable peace. But what about conflicts and the plurality of deeply held religious and philosophic worldviews?

Midwife To An Evolving Extraterrestrial Society

      The TO would serve as midwife to an evolving Extraterrestrial Society.

      What seems to me both practical and fair in this context is to think in terms of an Extraterrestrial Society of Intentional Communities. The previous analyses in sections 6 and 7 are suggestive. Each Intentional Community would have to work within the framework of peace established immediately above and as articulated in more detail below as “PFIT”; given such an Extraterrestrial Society framework of requirements, consider now the following with respect to Intentional Communities:

      Each person is free to found new (intentional) communities. Each Community would determine its own membership requirements. Each Community would have its own culture of liberties and responsibilities; a member would generally be free to leave the community. A mechanism or set of mechanisms would be established to insure that each member is fully and properly informed of their liberty to leave the (intentional) community. (I suppose some communities might still allow their members the possibility of experiencing serious physical pain – but they would also allow a member to voluntarily leave their community. Too, I suppose banning animal cruelty and serious animal pain would be desirable and feasible. At least at first, this might mean with respect to animals that only domesticated or farm animals would be allowed permanent residence in extraterrestrial space?)  

      Note that some ("hermit") communities would consist of only one person. On old Terra, it was often difficult or impossible to leave one's community – sometimes expulsion effectively meant the individual's death. The sustainable prosperous context of the Extraterrestrial Society of Intentional Communities is radically different. If in the unlikely event this turns out not to be the case, then TO may not work exactly as envisioned by me. But whatever the case may be, the TO would have to be realistically flexible and convincingly knowledgeable of all relevant technology including on the cutting-edge and perhaps too the merely imaginable.  

        So at the level of the Society (of Communities) we have: (1) Peace: Weapons, weapons-making, and violence (including animal cruelty and serious animal pain) are strongly effectively enforceably banned (and so-called “research” would not be permitted as a way to get around the ban); and, (2) Freedom: Every individual person is fully aware of and fully informed of their general liberty to leave their community. This too is strongly effectively enforced. The Society and the communities necessarily work closely together to fully insure the liberties and responsibilities associated with both Peace and Freedom. Also note that since there is "unlimited free land,” this fact will additionally help prevent some old terra-style conflicts and resolve or manage others (this would include some old-style civil conflicts).

        At the level of Communities (in the Society) we have: (1) Intentionality (voluntariness): Within the good-faith transparent enforcement of Society's basic principles of peace and freedom, each Community has wide latitude for experimentation. Although there is a general liberty of members to leave the (intentional) Community, this does not necessarily relieve such persons from certain good-faith responsibilities to the Community; and, (2) Transparency (accountability): Each Community must strongly, effectively, and transparently help enforce the Society's basic principles of peace and freedom.

        I believe the political theory or moral-political approach I have invented above with respect to TO is unique and original. The “PFIT” (Peaceful, Free, Intentional, Transparent) framework here presented differs from the "Law of Peoples" conception of John Rawls in that TO is meant to be structured so as to necessarily ultimately generate an Extraterrestrial Law of Persons. Yet TO takes seriously the distinction Rawls makes between a "political conception" and "comprehensive doctrines." A political conception or model addresses persons only with respect to, or at the level of, citizenship. However, comprehensive doctrines or worldviews, whether religious or secular, address the full range, or deep levels, of one’s personhood and relationships. In my "Society of Communities" theory, Society corresponds to a political conception or model, and Communities represent numerous comprehensive doctrines or worldviews.          

        “Is stable peace possible if each person or each people is passionately convinced that their worldview is basically good and correct – and that other worldviews are evil or bad or incorrect?”  If you can sincerely and in good faith agree to my TO political conception (my approach above), the answer to this question appears to be YES, such stable peace is possible. If you can at most only agree to my TO approach as a temporary compromise, then the answer may be NO.

      That is to say: Persons of Comprehensive Doctrine X may be passionately convinced that their worldview is basically good and correct – and that other worldviews are evil or bad or incorrect. Likewise, persons of Comprehensive Doctrine Y may be passionately convinced that their worldview is basically good and correct – and that other worldviews are evil or bad or incorrect. YET if X persons, Y persons, and other persons (holding numerous differing comprehensive doctrines) can sincerely and in good faith agree to my TO political conception (my approach above), then stable peace is possible. Otherwise, they may consider agreeing to TO only as a temporary strategic compromise (thus ultimately open to future use of force and violence).

      Accordingly, a major part of my TO or PFIT political conception is that the Treaty must be strongly effectively enforced by TO’s Agency for a Better Cosmos (ABC) – NOT by Peoples/States – against ALL and EVERYONE, whether or not they sign the Treaty. As Camus says in The Rebel: “Rebellion is in no way the demand for total freedom. On the contrary, … the rebel wants it to be recognized that freedom has its limits everywhere that a human being is to be found … The more aware rebellion is of demanding a just limit, the more inflexible it becomes. … The freedom he claims, he claims for all; the freedom he refuses, he forbids everyone to enjoy. He is not only the slave against the master, but also man against the world of master and slave.” (1991: 284)

     Our proposal for extraterrestrial peace and freedom may be likened to an unswerving arrow in that it has a strong and effective enforcement mechanism (TO’s Agency for a Better Cosmos). As Camus said: “The more aware rebellion is of demanding a just limit, the more inflexible it becomes.” (1991: 284) Indeed, the final sentence of The Rebel concludes (1991: 306): “At the moment of supreme tension, there will leap into flight an unswerving arrow, a shaft that is inflexible and free.”

      "If we could enforceably prevent each and every person from killing any person over a conflict (say, a conflict of worldviews) would we do so? If so, how would we resolve our conflicts?" If you can sincerely and in good faith (instead of merely as a temporary compromise) agree to my TO approach above, then stable peace in extraterrestrial space seems both possible and desirable. This approach, so I believe, realistically outlines a structure of stable peace for World Society and local Communities in extraterrestrial space – pointing toward conflict management in the new framework and encouraging subsequent projects to invent needed specifics.

      According to TO, the architectures of extraterrestrial settlements will have to be PFIT (Peaceful, Free, Intentional, Transparent). Indeed, the architectures of all extraterrestrial structures will have to be congruent with PFIT. TO, via TO’s ABC (Agency for a Better Cosmos), will proactively enforce the PFIT requirements. TO and ABC will have to be on the cutting edge of such changing technologies if they are to successfully fulfill their missions. PFIT preplanning and PFIT retrofitting of PFIT extraterrestrial settlements and structures will be an ongoing task.

§12   Extraterrestrial Turning Point

      The (increasingly suicidal?) political structure of island Earth, which is neither a Law of Peoples nor a Law of Persons, is unworkable. But at this unique point in history it is both desirable and feasible to establish a Terrestrial Law of Peoples (via the UP proposal). The (dangerously underdeveloped?) political structure of extraterrestrial Space, which is neither a Law of Peoples nor a Law of Persons, is unworkable. But at this unique point in history it is both desirable and feasible to establish a Treaty Organization of peoples structured so as to necessarily ultimately generate an Extraterrestrial Law of Persons (via the TO proposal).  

     At this doubly-unique terrestrial-extraterrestrial point in world history, UP-TO is politically doable. World posterity would be eternally grateful to the EU and others for playing leading roles in birthing the joint UP-TO project. A window of opportunity has opened to the world. It is an open invitation for the world to achieve peace, freedom, and prosperity for the first time in history.

§13   From Man-unkind to Meridian-kind?

      Beyond the UP-TO task, now for some more expansive remarks with respect to Omniverse Theory and its related projects. Broadly speaking, Meridian Rebellion can be said to support and enrich Omniverse Theory; let me explain further. Three such Camus/ Camusian insights are: (1.) I rebel, therefore we exist; (2.) We are alone; and, (3.) Live and let live.  Omniverse Theorists would interpret or re-interpret these insights so as not to forfeit their ontological intimations: the omniverse, abstracted from a “My-I” perspective, has both temporal (contingent) and paragonal (non-contingent/ axiological) realms or aspects. Thus when the Meridian Rebels pragmatically maintain that we are alone, the Omniverse Theorists will add contextual brackets as follows: “Virtue cannot separate itself from [temporal] reality without becoming a principle of evil. Nor can it identify itself completely with [temporal] reality without denying itself.” (1991: 296)

      Additional insights (as well as the UP-TO Project) have been articulated above based on Meridian Rebellion (and Omniverse Theory). We have individual-rights to life-liberty; likewise we have mutual-obligations of life-liberty. If we have individual-rights to life-liberty, then we have mutual-obligations to create and sustain such a world society.

      We are mutually obligated to create and sustain a world society of life-liberty. Edmund Burke in 1790 pointed out that society is “a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born.” Accordingly, with Meridian Rebellion and Omniverse Theory in mind, we must be committed to a perpetually evolving world society at stable peace with enduring freedom for everyone, including the dead. The ethical imperative to develop a science-technology with the ability to resurrect all of the dead is part of Omniverse Theory, and the imperative is provided with further motivational and epistemological support from Meridian Rebellion.     

      Camus realizes that Meridian Rebellion (rebellion with limits) changes everything. Our common nature (“I rebel, therefore we are”) applies not only to humans present and past – but also to our offspring, to those transhumans and posthumans of the eras that come after the Technological Singularity (famously predicted by Vernor Vinge to be a 21st century occurrence: “the imminent creation by technology of entities with greater-than-human intelligence”). Thus it seems, in apparent contradiction to some predictions, that it is NOT the case that we know nothing whatsoever about post-Singularity realities. According to Camus, perhaps we may be able to turn science-technology around so as to serve life-liberty instead of death-ideology. Camus does not believe that this Ethical Singularity or moral imperative or “terrible necessity” is guaranteed even if it were “possible” – but in the event it should occur: “This terrible necessity [technology for living instead of for dying] will mark the decisive turning-point” in history. (1991: 295)

      Future persons (as did previous persons) have mutual obligations (as do “present” persons) to future and “present” persons – and to previous persons. In the words of Camus: “All may indeed live again, … but on condition that it is understood that they correct one another, and that a limit, under the sun, shall curb them all.” (1991: 306)  After the Singularity, as before, attempting to exist either above or below the meridian serves death instead of life. The alternative is Meridiankind, a perpetually evolving mutual adventure society of life and liberty.

§14   Closing Remarks

Predicting rain doesn't count, building arks does.

-- Warren Buffett

      This article added more support and depth to Omniverse Theory (Tandy 2009). We looked at the philosophic works of Albert Camus and concluded that they provide further axiological insight helpful to the ethical-political development and application of Omniverse Theory. With such Camusian insights in mind, we expanded Omniverse Theory with respect to pragmatic proposals meant to improve terrestrial society, ban extraterrestrial weapons, and proactively structure an extraterrestrial world at stable peace fit for free persons living in self-sufficient green-habitat intentional communities. Conceptually, it was found that individual rights are ethically required and that these individual rights in turn ethically require mutual obligations. Such a perpetually-evolving peaceful-and-free world society (“Meridiankind”) cuts across generations, generating an ethical imperative to develop anti-death science-technology with the ability to resurrect all of the dead.

Acknowledgements

      I would like to thank Dr. Glen Harold Stassen (Fuller Theological Seminary) for first introducing me to the thoughts of Albert Camus and of John Rawls more than four decades ago. Part A above is adapted from (Tandy 2010b); and, Part C above is adapted from (Tandy 2010c).

 

NOTES

 

1 But see below: “§4. Camus And Anti-Absurdity: The Rebel” (see specifically the subsection: “Part Five Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Thought At The Meridian”).

 

2 With reference to my UP-TO related research, I would like to thank the philosophy department of National Chung Cheng University (Taiwan) for their “Visiting Scholar” assistance. I am also grateful to Giorgio Baruchello, Al Globus, Jack Lee, and Asher Seidel for their comments on earlier drafts or partial drafts. For previous UP-TO related work by me, see for example the reprint of my 2007 article – Chapter 13 (pages 177-188) of Charles Tandy, 21st Century Clues: Essays in Ethics, Ontology, and Time Travel (Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, 2010). Also see: <http://www.segits.com>.

 

3 Much of the UP section of this paper (§10) is based in part on John Rawls, The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001).

 

4 See The American Interest (January-February 2007). The article by Ivo Daalder and James Lindsay (“Democracies of the World, Unite”) is available at <http://www.the-american-interest.com/article.cfm?piece=220>.

 

5 Part of my inspiration for the TO idea comes from Dr. Carol Rosin and her website at <http://www.peaceinspace.com>.

 

6 “Extraterrestrial O’Neill Habitats” (or “SEG communities”) – See, for example: (A) P. Ulmschneider, “O’Neill-Type Space Habitats and the Industrial Conquest of Space,” Chapter 16 in Charles Tandy (editor), Death And Anti-Death, Volume 7 (Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, 2009). (B) Seg-communities, <www.ria.edu/seg-communities> (2008). (C) P. Ulmschneider, Intelligent Life in the Universe, Principles and Requirements Behind Its Emergence (2nd ed.: Heidelberg, Berlin: Springer Verlag, 2006). (D) Gerard K. O’Neill, The High Frontier: Human Colonies in Space (3rd ed.: Burlington, Ontario, Canada: Apogee Books, 2000). (E) J. S. Lewis, Mining the Sky (Reading, Massachusetts: Helix Books, Addison-Wesley, 1997). (F) C. T. Kowal, Asteroids, Their Nature and Utilization (Chichester: Ellis, 1988). (G) G. Harry Stein, The Third Industrial Revolution (New York: Ace Books, 1979). (H) T. A. Heppenheimer, Colonies in Space (Harrisburg, Pennsylvania: Stackpole Books, 1977). (For a more complete bibliography, see: <http://spaceset.org/p.bib.mm>.)

 

7 “Molecular Drexler Technology” – Molecular nanotechnology’s founder and founding book is K. Eric Drexler, Engines of Creation (New York: Anchor Press, 1987). This book is available free on the internet. Also see, for example: (A) Judith Light Feather and Miguel F. Aznar, Nanoscience Education, Workforce Training, and K-12 Resources. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2010). (B) Gabor L. Hornyak et al., Introduction to Nanoscience. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2008). (C) Linda Williams and Wade Adams, Nanotechnology Demystified. (New York: McGraw-Hill Professional, 2006). (D) J. Storrs Hall, Nanofuture: What's Next for Nanotechnology. (New York: Prometheus Books, 2005). (E) Mark A. Ratner and Daniel Ratner, Nanotechnology: A Gentle Introduction to the Next Big Idea. (New York: Prentice Hall, 2002). (F) Mick Wilson et al., Nanotechnology: Basic Science and Emerging Technologies. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2002).

 

8 For such quotations as in this paragraph, see the websites Spaceflight or Extinction <http://www.spaext.com> and Space Quotes to Ponder <http://www.spacequotes.com>.

 

 

REFERENCES

 

Asimov, I. 1991, Asimov's Chronology of the World. New York: Harper Collins Publishers. [See the Epilog.]

 

Buffett, W. 2011, [Quotation: “Predicting rain doesn't count, building arks does.”] <http://www.quotationspage.com/quote/32917.html>.

 

Buford, T. O. 1984, Personal Philosophy: The Art of Living. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

 

Burke, E. 1790, Reflections on the Revolution in France. <http://www.constitution.org/eb/rev_fran.htm>.

[“SOCIETY is indeed ... a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born.”]

 

Camus, A. 1955, “Preface” [pages v-vi of:] The Myth of Sisyphus, and Other Essays. New York: Vintage/Random House. 1955/1983/1991 [Translated from the French by Justin O’Brien.]

 

Camus, A. 1991, The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt. UK: Vintage Books. [Originally published in French in 1954.]

 

Camus, A. 2005, The Myth of Sisyphus. London: Penguin Books. [Originally published in French in 1942.]

 

Carter, V. and Dale, T. 1974, Topsoil and Civilization. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press. [See page 12.]

 

Daalder, I. and Lindsay, J. 2007, “Democracies of the World, Unite,” The American Interest (January-February 2007). Available free on the internet: <http://www.the-american-interest.com/article.cfm?piece=220>.

 

Diamond, J. 2005,  Collapse: How Societies Choose to Fail or Succeed. New York: Viking.

 

Drexler, K. E. 1986, Engines of Creation. New York: Anchor Press. Available free on the internet.

 

Evans, J. D. G. 1995, “Prisoner’s Dilemma,” in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Ted Honderich, Editor), Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

 

Feather, J. L., and Aznar, M. F.  2010, Nanoscience Education, Workforce Training, and K-12 Resources, Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.

 

Ford, B. J. 2009, “Culturing Meat For The Future: Anti-Death Versus Anti-Life,” In Tandy, C. [Editor] (2009). Death And Anti-Death, Volume 7: Nine Hundred Years After St. Anselm (1033-1109), Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, pp. 55-80.

 

Gore, A. 2006, An Inconvenient Truth: The Planetary Emergency of Global Warming and What We Can Do About It, Emmaus, Pennsylvania: Rodale Books. [This is the first book in history produced to offset 100% of the CO2 emissions generated from production activities with renewable energy; this publication is carbon-neutral.]

 

Hall, J. S. 2005, Nanofuture: What's Next for Nanotechnology, New York: Prometheus Books.

 

Heppenheimer, T. A. 1977, Colonies in Space, Harrisburg, Pennsylvania: Stackpole Books.

 

Hornyak, G. L., et al. 2008, Introduction to Nanoscience, Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.

 

Kowal, C. T.  1988, Asteroids, Their Nature and Utilization, Chichester: Ellis.

 

Lewis, J. S. 1997, Mining the Sky, Reading, MA: Helix Books, Addison-Wesley.

 

Lyotard, Jean-Francois. 1984, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

 

O’Neill, G. K.  2000, The High Frontier: Human Colonies in Space, Burlington, Ontario, Canada: Apogee Books. (3rd edition). Also see: <http://www.nss.org/resources/books/ non_fiction/review_008_highfrontier.html>.

 

Ratner, M. A., and Ratner, D.  2002, Nanotechnology: A Gentle Introduction to the Next Big Idea, New York: Prentice Hall.

 

Rawls, J. 1971, A Theory Of Justice, Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press Of Harvard University Press. Revised Edition, 1999. (Original Edition, 1971).

 

Rawls, J. 1999, The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. This edition, 2001.

 

Rosen, C. 2009, The Institute for Cooperation in Space (website): <http://www.peaceinspace.com>.

 

Schmookler, A. B. 1984, The Parable of the Tribes, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Company.

 

Seg-communities.  2008, <http://www.ria.edu/seg-communities>. [Seg-communities = Self-sufficient Extra-terrestrial Green-habitats, or O’Neill communities.]

 

Sen, A. 1999, Development as Freedom, New York: Anchor Books. This edition, 2000.

 

Spaceflight or Extinction. 2010, <http://www.spaext.com>.

 

Space Quotes to Ponder. 2010,  <http://www.spacequotes.com>.

 

Spaceset. 2010, [Bibliography.] <http://spaceset.org/p.bib.mm>.

 

Stein, G. H. 1979, The Third Industrial Revolution, New York: Ace Books.

 

Tandy, C. 2004, "Earthlings Get Off Your Ass Now!: Becoming Person, Learning Community," In Tandy, C. (Editor), Death And Anti-Death, Volume 2: Two Hundred Years After Kant, Fifty Years After Turing, Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, pp. 373-391.

 

Tandy, C. 2006/2011, “‘Wild-West’ Versus ‘Space-Age’ Systems Science: An Extraterrestrial Prisoner’s Dilemma?” <http://www.ria.edu/papers/wildwest/index.htm>.

 

Tandy, C. 2009, “Omniverse in the First Person,” Applied Ethics Review 47, pp.1-42.

 

Tandy, C. 2010a, 21st Century Clues: Essays in Ethics, Ontology, and Time Travel, Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press.

 

Tandy, C. 2010b, “Camusian Thoughts About The Ultimate Question Of Life," In Tandy, Charles (Editor), Death And Anti-Death, Volume 8: Fifty Years After Albert Camus (1913-1960), Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, pp. 379-400.

 

Tandy, C. 2010c, “The UP-TO Project: How To Achieve World Peace, Freedom, And Prosperity,” In Tandy, Charles (Editor), Death And Anti-Death, Volume 8: Fifty  Years After Albert Camus (1913-1960), Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, pp. 401-418.

 

Ulmschneider, P.  2006, Intelligent Life in the Universe, Principles and Requirements Behind Its Emergence, 2nd Ed. Heidelberg, Berlin: Springer Verlag.

 

Ulmschneider, P.  2009, “O’Neill-Type Space Habitats and the Industrial Conquest of Space,” In Tandy, C. [Editor] (2009). Death And Anti-Death, Volume 7: Nine Hundred Years After St. Anselm (1033-1109), Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, pp. 469-494.

 

Vinge, V.1993/2003/2011, [His famous “Technological Singularity” article.]

<http://www-rohan.sdsu.edu/faculty/vinge/misc/WER2.html>.

[“the imminent creation by technology of entities with greater-than-human intelligence.”]

 

Voltaire. 1767, [Wrote to Frederick the Great: "Doubt is not a pleasant condition, but certainty is an absurd one."] <http://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Voltaire>.

 

Watson, B. 1964, Han Fei Tzu: Basic Writings, New York: Columbia University Press.

 

Williams, L. and Adams, W. 2006, Nanotechnology Demystified, New York: McGraw-Hill Professional.

 

Wilson, M., et al. 2002, Nanotechnology: Basic Science and Emerging Technologies, Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press. 

------------------------------

OMNIVERSE THEORY WEBPAGES

 

§ TOP OF PAGE [before PART ONE]

§ PART ONE [“Omniverse In The First Person”]

§ PART TWO [“Extraterrestrial Turning Point”] (PART TWO IS ON ITS OWN WEBPAGE)

§ SOME RECENT WORKS BY DR. TANDY [list of works]

§ SOME ADDITIONAL RELATED WORKS [list of works]

 

(PART TWO IS ON ITS OWN WEBPAGE: THE PRESENT PAGE)



[1] But see below: “§4. Camus And Anti-Absurdity: The Rebel” (see specifically the subsection: “Part Five Of Five Parts Is Entitled: Thought At The Meridian”).

[2] With reference to my UP-TO related research, I would like to thank the philosophy department of National Chung Cheng University (Taiwan) for their “Visiting Scholar” assistance. I am also grateful to Giorgio Baruchello, Al Globus, Jack Lee, and Asher Seidel for their comments on earlier drafts or partial drafts. For previous UP-TO related work by me, see for example the reprint of my 2007 article – Chapter 13 (pages 177-188) of Charles Tandy, 21st Century Clues: Essays in Ethics, Ontology, and Time Travel (Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, 2010). Also see: <http://www.segits.com>.

[3] Much of the UP section of this paper (§10) is based in part on John Rawls, The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001).

[4] See The American Interest (January-February 2007). The article by Ivo Daalder and James Lindsay (“Democracies of the World, Unite”) is available at <http://www.the-american-interest.com/article.cfm?piece=220>.

[5] Part of my inspiration for the TO idea comes from Dr. Carol Rosin and her website at <http://www.peaceinspace.com>.

[6] “Extraterrestrial O’Neill Habitats” (or “SEG communities”) – See, for example: (A) P. Ulmschneider, “O’Neill-Type Space Habitats and the Industrial Conquest of Space,” Chapter 16 in Charles Tandy (editor), Death And Anti-Death, Volume 7 (Palo Alto, California: Ria University Press, 2009). (B) Seg-communities, <www.ria.edu/seg-communities> (2008). (C) P. Ulmschneider, Intelligent Life in the Universe, Principles and Requirements Behind Its Emergence (2nd ed.: Heidelberg, Berlin: Springer Verlag, 2006). (D) Gerard K. O’Neill, The High Frontier: Human Colonies in Space (3rd ed.: Burlington, Ontario, Canada: Apogee Books, 2000). (E) J. S. Lewis, Mining the Sky (Reading, Massachusetts: Helix Books, Addison-Wesley, 1997). (F) C. T. Kowal, Asteroids, Their Nature and Utilization (Chichester: Ellis, 1988). (G) G. Harry Stein, The Third Industrial Revolution (New York: Ace Books, 1979). (H) T. A. Heppenheimer, Colonies in Space (Harrisburg, Pennsylvania: Stackpole Books, 1977). (For a more complete bibliography, see: <http://spaceset.org/p.bib.mm>.)

[7] “Molecular Drexler Technology” – Molecular nanotechnology’s founder and founding book is K. Eric Drexler, Engines of Creation (New York: Anchor Press, 1987). This book is available free on the internet. Also see, for example: (A) Judith Light Feather and Miguel F. Aznar, Nanoscience Education, Workforce Training, and K-12 Resources. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2010). (B) Gabor L. Hornyak et al., Introduction to Nanoscience. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2008). (C) Linda Williams and Wade Adams, Nanotechnology Demystified. (New York: McGraw-Hill Professional, 2006). (D) J. Storrs Hall, Nanofuture: What's Next for Nanotechnology. (New York: Prometheus Books, 2005). (E) Mark A. Ratner and Daniel Ratner, Nanotechnology: A Gentle Introduction to the Next Big Idea. (New York: Prentice Hall, 2002). (F) Mick Wilson et al., Nanotechnology: Basic Science and Emerging Technologies. (Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2002).

[8] For such quotations as in this paragraph, see the websites Spaceflight or Extinction <http://www.spaext.com> and Space Quotes to Ponder <http://www.spacequotes.com>.